Contact a Humanities Office or Academic unit.
Find your course outlines.

Philosophy Department Speaker Series

Fall Term, 2019

Unless announced otherwise, all lectures will be held on Fridays at 3:30pm

in BSB 138

 

13 September: Richard Healey

Immoral Promises”

 Abstract: An important feature of our power to promise is that we have significant latitude in deciding the content of the promises we make. We can promise to perform an indefinite range of actions in an indefinite range of contexts and with varying degrees of solemnity. In this talk I investigate how far this latitude extends. In particular, I ask whether some promises fail to bind in virtue of their immoral content. For example, can I make a morally binding promise to you to kill an innocent person? I aim to show that there are notable drawbacks to the positions held by those on both sides of this debate, and then begin – tentatively – to develop a better account.

 


20 September: Robert Stern (University of Sheffield)

“A Moral Argument against Freedom”

Abstract: A moral argument against free choice, which draws on Luther to argue that the good moral agent has no choice about how to act, as for them following the good is the only option – so the moral agent lacks free will in this sense. I contrast this argument with more traditional determinist arguments against freedom, and also consider how this view still leaves room for responsibility and imputation.

 


27 September: Wil Waluchow (McMaster University)

“The Misconceived Quest for the Elusive Right Answer Or Dedication to a Process, Not a Result” 

Abstract: Among the long-standing questions of legal theory is whether judges ever make new law when they decide legal cases. Many legal theorists believe that judge-made law is inevitable, perhaps even desirable. They think this is so even in modern constitutional democracies rooted in the common law, where deliberation and voting among elected legislators is widely accepted as the principal means through which laws are created.  Other legal theorists reject both the necessity and desirability of judge-made law. Ronald Dworkin was perhaps the foremost contemporary proponent of this view and set out to develop a complex theory that purports to eliminate the need for judges ever to create new law. According to Dworkin’s famous right answer thesis, there is always, in a mature legal system, an antecedently existing right answer to the pivotal legal question on which a case might turn. And it is the duty of the judge to find and apply it in deciding her case. Democratic legitimacy demands nothing less.  It is the aim of this paper to dispute the necessity of right answers. I will argue that democratic legitimacy may not, contra Dworkin, require antecedently pre-existing right answers. In developing this argument, my focus will be on constitutional cases involving charters of rights, where the possibility of significant indeterminac, and hence judicial creativity, loom large. The worry is that judges, in applying the abstract, morally charged provisions found in charters of rights, invariably make the law up as they go along, thus threatening the democratic legitimacy of their decisions. Indeed, the worry is that discretionary decision-making at this level will undermine entirely the very legitimacy of our constitutional democracies and the institutions of judicial review they typically include. My aim is to go some way towards quieting this worry by arguing that legitimacy may not always require right answers. In many instances it may require only that answers be derived in the right way.

 


4 October: Sonia Sikka (University of Ottawa)

“Should we abolish religious freedom”

Abstract: Religious freedom has long been a protected right in liberal democratic nations and is standardly included within international conventions on human rights.  Freedom of thought and association are basic liberal principles, but the naming and institution of religious freedom in particular singles out religion as a unique category of belief and practice, requiring special protection – as well as special exclusion, we should note, via the correlative principle of secularism.  Is this singling out legitimate?  Is there truly something unique about religious belief, identity and/or practice that warrants special regulative measures?  Or is the existence of such measures merely the artefact of a specific period of Western history?

I argue that, in operation, the legal and political positioning of religion as subject to special protection as well as exclusion is not warranted and can have pernicious effects.  In practice, legislative guarantees of religious freedom tend to privilege and thereby incentivize particular forms of religion at the expense of others.  In addition, courts and legislators have been increasingly hard-pressed to determine what counts as “religion” and to justify accommodative measures for religious beliefs over non-religious ones.  In many cases, terms such as “belief,” “lack of belief,” and “philosophical belief” have been added to protections for religion, which have often already included conscience, but these modifications raise the question of whether religion should be taken as paradigmatic for the protections in question.  I propose that we should move towards a model based on the broader principle of protection for minority beliefs and practices against laws of general application that purport to be neutral but are the product of majoritarian decision-making processes that sometimes compromise equality.

 


11 October: No Speaker


18 October:Reading Week – No Speaker


25 October: Ethan Meanor (McMaster University)

“Nietzsche and Gorgias on Non-Being”

ABSTRACT: The rejection of the concept of “being” is one of Nietzsche’s central philosophical commitments, and he makes much of the affinity between himself and Heraclitus on this point. He seems, however, to have overlooked the fact that this rejection has another important precursor in Gorgias of Leontini (c. 483-375 B.C.), who argued in his lost work On Non-Being that there is no being, and that even if there is, it cannot be known. Despite the striking similarities between many of their arguments, almost no scholarly attention has been paid to the affinity between Nietzsche and Gorgias. I show not only that they both reject the concept of “being” as incoherent, but that they further deny the capacity of concepts to adequately represent reality. I go on to consider the different ways in which Gorgias and Nietzsche respond to these conclusions: the former by renouncing philosophy because it can never arrive at the truth about being, the latter by attempting to conceive of philosophy as aiming not at the attainment of such a truth, but at the most comprehensive interpretation of reality that is possible within the limits of human thought. I suggest that Nietzsche makes an innovation insofar as he is able to see a way forward for philosophy even in the face of skepticism about being, which Gorgias apparently was not. But, this difference notwithstanding, their arguments against being belong together in the history of ideas. It is only unfortunate that, in tracing his philosophical lineage back to Heraclitus, Nietzsche overlooked another important ancestor. I hope that this study goes some way toward correcting that oversight.

 


1 November: Charlie Cooper-Simpson (University of Toronto)

Abstract to Follow

 


8 November: Gary Hatfield (University of Pennsylvania)

“Phenomenally Converging Railway Tracks: A Misperception?”

Abstract: Railway tracks appear to converge into the distance. Is this appearance a misperception? Typically, observers don’t believe that they do converge physically. These statements thus far are consistent with treating the apparent convergence as a case of illusion, like the Mueller-Lyer illusion. One line looks longer than the other, an appearance widely considered to be illusory, yet we are not taken in and so we don’t misperceive in the sense of making a false judgment about the actual length of the lines – or about the actual physical width between the tracks. Here, one might say that there is phenomenal misperception of line length but no judgmental misperception. Good enough. But I intend to pursue the idea that the converging train tracks are not a misperception in this phenomenal sense. Construing them as a misperception depends, in my estimation, on a particular task analysis of phenomenal perception: that it aims to present physical scenes in a way that conforms to their mind-independent physical structure. This is a widely held conception, found in theorists as disparate as Gibson and Burge. My idea is that the contraction of visual space, as with the tracks, is not a mistake brought about by inadequate information about distance, but rather a phenomenal accommodation of the decreasing information with distance, an accommodation that presents the tracks in a manner which reveals action-guiding information and is ecologically efficient.

 


15 November: Kristin Gjesdal (Temple University)

Abstract to Follow

 


22 November: Aaron Preston

Abstract to Follow

 


29 November: Cheryl Misak (University of Toronto)

Abstract to Follow

 



   Visiting Speaker Series 2018-2019

  Visiting Speaker Series 2017-2018

Visiting Speaker Series 2016-2017

Visiting Speaker Series 2015-2016

Visiting Speaker Series 2014-2015

Visiting Speaker Series 2013-2014

Visiting Speaker Series 2012-2013

Visiting Speaker Series 2011-2012